As cognitive neuroscience increases its dominion, its
proponents have made grandiose claims for its utility. There is nothing new
about this. Scientists have always claimed that their new discoveries could
save the world.
These claims have often been greeted with doubt and even
derision. Some have labeled scientists’ pretense to solve all of the great
mysteries of life as scientism.
Science has made great progress. Through the intermediary of
technology and industrialization, it has vastly improved the quality of human
life over the past few centuries. Surely, that does not mean that we should
allow science or scientists to dictate personal behavior, public policies and
God knows what else.
Yesterday in The New Republic Harvard psychologist Steven Pinker took out after those who dared claim that he or any of his colleagues
was practicing scientism. He offered a spirited defense of the value of
science and explained the lessons that we ought to be drawing from it. Shortly
thereafter, Ross Douthat took to his New York Times blog to offer a fine
rejoinder. Both essays are well worth your attention.
The issues are complex and difficult. Pinker begins by
crediting science for the Enlightenment and the Age of Reason. He neglects to
mention the Industrial Revolution, but we will forgive the oversight.
He opens his essay thusly:
The
great thinkers of the Age of Reason and the Enlightenment were scientists. Not
only did many of them contribute to mathematics, physics, and physiology, but
all of them were avid theorists in the sciences of human nature.
Among these great thinkers were, Pinker says, Descartes and
Hume.
While it was certainly true that Descartes was a scientist,
his most important philosophical works involved deducing the existence of a pure
metaphysical subject, a mind. If you read his Meditations you will discover that his effort did not, in any way
use scientific reasoning. In fact, Descartes separated the mind from reality-driven perceptions and sensations. The Cartesian mind had nothing to do with empirical
evidence and was not verifiable.
As for Hume, one recalls vividly the eighteenth century
British philosopher’s distinction between science and ethics. If science is the
realm of what is and ethics is the realm of what we should or should not to,
the two are not at all the same.
Science can tell you what happens when you shoot a bullet
into a vat of jelly. It can also tell you want happens when you shoot a bullet
into someone’s head. It does not tell you whether you should or should not do
the one or the other.
Scientific information may aid our moral reflections, but
the question of whether or not to shoot a gun remains outside of its scope.
After all, there is a significant moral distinction between shooting someone
who is minding his own business and shooting someone who is lunging at you with
an axe.
Where Descartes said that the only thing we know to an absolute
certainty is that we are thinking, Pinker claimed that science has provided us
with a bevy of indisputable facts.
Among them he lists these:
We
know, but our ancestors did not, that humans belong to a single species of
African primate that developed agriculture, government, and writing late in its
history. We know that our species is a tiny twig of a genealogical tree that
embraces all living things and that emerged from prebiotic chemicals almost
four billion years ago. We know that we live on a planet that revolves around
one of a hundred billion stars in our galaxy, which is one of a hundred billion
galaxies in a 13.8-billion-year-old universe, possibly one of a vast number of
universes.
Even if we grant this, what precisely is the relevance?
Surely, these facts are intended to undermine any human claims to
self-importance, but religions have always been at war against excessive human
pride.
As for knowing that we all belong to the same species, thus
that we are all human beings, how important is that really?
Unless we are true-believing humanists like Steven Pinker,
we normally do not define our identity in terms of our biology. We are
Americans or Canadians, we belong to the Harvard faculty or to the legal
profession; we belong to this or that religious congregation.
Our social being cannot be defined by our membership in the
species because being human, in the biological sense, does not require anything
of us. You do not cease to be human if you behave badly and you do not become
more human if you behave well. For all intents and purposes your
membership in the human species requires nothing of you.
Pinker does try to sneak the moral dimension back in by
defining people as members of a community of humanists who believe that their
ethical beliefs are informed by science.
Pinker is aware of the clear distinction between science and
ethics, but he downplays it:
Though
the scientific facts do not by themselves dictate values, they certainly hem in
the possibilities. By stripping ecclesiastical authority of its credibility on
factual matters, they cast doubt on its claims to certitude in matters of
morality. The scientific refutation of the theory of vengeful gods and occult
forces undermines practices such as human sacrifice, witch hunts, faith
healing, trial by ordeal, and the persecution of heretics.
What does that mean: "hem in the possibilities?" The possible
consequences of your actions are always somewhat limited. We use such
information to make better decisions. But that does not mean that science
determines our decisions. Even if science tells you exactly what happens when
you shoot someone in the head, it still does not tell you whether or not you
should do it.
Clearly, Galileo stripped ecclesiastical authority of its
credibility on factual matters, but why does that necessarily strip religious
leaders of their credibility of matters of faith and morals, that is, on
matters that are not based on fact.
Surely, Pinker is correct to disparage many religious
practices. One would feel more comfortable if he also called out some of the
strange beliefs that scientists have been peddling since the dawn of time. He also should have listed the positive contributions that religions have made to human
community.
Still, he does not seem to recognize that you cannot prove
or disprove the existence of God scientifically. How precisely would you go
about applying science to an entity that contains no measurable or testable
characteristics? How would you demonstrate that an afterlife does or does not exist?
If you limit your study to metaphysical objects like
ideas, objects that no one has ever seen, heard, tasted, touched or smelled…
how can you gain scientific knowledge about objects that cannot be measured or tested?
Pinker understands these difficulties, so he uses a sleight-of-hand when he tries to show how science can help generate the moral
principles that he prefers.
He writes:
The
facts of science, by exposing the absence of purpose in the laws governing the
universe, force us to take responsibility for the welfare of ourselves, our
species, and our planet.
All things considered, the one does not in any way follow
from the other. The facts of science do not force us to do anything.
As Douthat notes, Pinker is practicing his own form of
scientism. He is using the authority of science to promote and impose his own
moral principles.
If we are as small and insignificant as science says we are,
why would we not think it futile to waste our precious time taking
responsibility for the welfare of everything that moves? And where in science
does Pinker find the concept of responsibility anyway?
Happily for Pinker science seems to eliminate the metaphysical notion of
free will. This makes it much easier to force people to do what you want them
to do.
Pinker has taken a remarkable leap of faith. Normally, we
care more for friends than strangers. We normally defend our families and our
nations before we defend anyone else’s family or nation. Why should we humans feel
responsible for every blooming member of the species, to say nothing about the
planet?
Isn’t Pinker promoting his own personal form of idolatry?
After paying lip service to these concerns, Pinker skips
effortlessly into the notion that scientific facts “militate” for the
establishment of a new code of human conduct that must “maximize the
flourishing of humans and other sentient beings.” Can we really maximize our own "flourishing"or even happiness while working to maximize the flourishing of frogs and turtles?
In his words:
And in
combination with a few unexceptionable convictions— that all of us value our
own welfare and that we are social beings who impinge on each other and can
negotiate codes of conduct—the scientific facts militate toward a defensible
morality, namely adhering to principles that maximize the flourishing of humans
and other sentient beings. This humanism, which is inextricable from a
scientific understanding of the world, is becoming the de facto morality of
modern democracies, international organizations, and liberalizing religions,
and its unfulfilled promises define the moral imperatives we face today.
It might well be the case that humanistic morality, the kind
that arises when people lose their place in their nations and local
communities, is taking over the democratic world today. But, does that mean that it should be?
On the subject of Stephen Pinker and science, see this: http://shadowtolight.wordpress.com/2013/07/15/steven-pinker-on-francis-collins/
ReplyDeleteand this: http://shadowtolight.wordpress.com/2013/08/07/steven-pinkers-subtle-attack-on-science/
ReplyDeleteAnd finally, to toot my own horn: http://shadowtolight.wordpress.com/2013/07/16/the-arbitrary-attack-on-free-will/
ReplyDeleteI think science does and will help us to figure out what is good and bad.
ReplyDeleteIt can tell us what is going on in our brains and bodies when we do certain things.
And it can track the big data and give us reports on people who do X as compared with people who do Y.
And people who think X compared to people who think Y.
It can also check out the dictates of religion.
For instance, God told the people of two religions not to eat bacon.
Unfortunately, he didn't give a reason but science can tell us if, healthwise, it's bad for you.
Science recognizes two forms of uncertainty at the boundary of determinism: fuzzy uncertainty and random processes.
ReplyDeleteActually the line between science and morality is fuzzy because one needs a causal or deterministic model to predict the outcome of actions, the will cannot function without an effort to reason, and reason is determinstic ideas with a bounded uncertainty!
Morality adds another uncertain dimension which is the perception of emotion as feedback to what is a good outcome and what is a bad outcome of any action or social process. If there are no emotions then nothing can be good or bad!
Emotions are individual evaluations made in a group context and no one can say how the body or brain forms a particular emotional filter. Free will is guided by reason and emotion which are not formed by acts of will. An abused child will have very different experiences of reason (causation) and emotion (evaluation of outcomes) then a well-parented child and these outcomes are not in the control of the will of the child in question.
The universe determines everything although the process by which this occurs is mysterious, this leads to the illusion of free will. In a narrow domain, within a context of favorable conditions, the body has a choice of action, when the rest of the universe reduces those choices (a stroke, a car crash) the ability to choose is impaired by degrees. Therefore free will is a temporary ability constrained on all sides by a natural process.
If science predicts disease or disability due to poor sanitation or medical practices, and society chooses to ignore the scientific causes and consequences, then by degrees the will of some people will be impaired, ethics then must decide if behavior of individuals must be constrained for the common good. Science is part and parcel of morality and ethics, not a separate thing.
The problem with Pinker is that he is arrogant and unaware that he doesn't know everything.
ReplyDeleteflourishing is a word we should all be afraid of as well
ReplyDeleteWe certainly should be afraid of that word. See my earlier post: http://stuartschneiderman.blogspot.com/2011/01/good-marriage-in-good-life.html
ReplyDeleteI'm smarter than you, so you should do as I say. Seems kinda what Pinker is saying.
ReplyDeleteMy answer: Btfsplk!
V chewy topic. The Greeks called it Hubris. Christians, False Pride. I'm sure other cultures recognized the problem.
ReplyDeleteEnlightenment & Scientific Rev. led to many great things. Great Good & Great Evil. Good: US. Evil: French Rev. & Napoleonic Wars. And so on.
I call myself an Agnostic Existentialist. I'm also with the Founding Fathers, who were v v cynical about Human Nature. Also Isaiah Berlin, who argued that many Ideas are irreconcilable.
I'm struck by Rousseau & Marx & their epigones. All were/are convinced of their absolute rightness and rectitude. All caused/cause terrible suffering & death.
As I see it, WCiv Elite zeitgeist is scientistic, antinomian, hubristic. It's a secular religion, with fetishes, devils, and saints.
I see evidence of that in Liberal magazines & websites (with ferocious Comments sections). In Academia, increasingly polarized politics, overweening govt. that seeks to mold its citizens rather than serve them.
Perhaps, as the world and Cosmos become more inscrutable and "absurd", our Leaders need to domesticate and rationalize us to their "scientific" standards.
When "The American People" was used in speeches, it used to mean something that everyone could understand. I'm not sure that's still the case. - Rich Lara