Sam Harris likes analogies. He has tried to demonstrate that
we create a science of value judgments by offer an analogy between well-being and health.
In one blog post, he compared taste with moral behavior:
If, for
instance, a preference for chocolate ice cream allowed for the most rewarding
experience a human being could have, while a preference for vanilla did not, we
would deem it morally important to help people overcome any defect in their
sense of taste that caused them to prefer vanilla—in the same way that we
currently treat people for curable forms of blindness. It seems to me that the
boundary between mere aesthetics and moral imperative—the difference between
not liking Matisse and not liking the Golden Rule—is more a matter of there
being higher stakes, and consequences that reach into the lives of others, than
of there being distinct classes of facts regarding the nature of human
experience.
Being a leading contemporary proponent of scientism— the belief that
science can resolve all problems by reducing human being to a measurable
mechanism—Harris reveals his wish, and not a scientific wish, to impose his
taste and his values on other people.
Surely, no rational individual would accept that preferring
vanilla to chocolate is a “defect” like blindness. Very few rational individuals
would accept that sensory pleasure is “the most rewarding experience a human
being could have.”
Why is Harris
thinking about how he can arrogate to himself the power—and it will require
power—to deprive people of the choice between vanilla and chocolate?
Do you really believe that we can establish scientifically
what is and what is not “the most rewarding experience” that a generic human
can have and that we should therefore grant someone—Sam Harris—the right to
impose that taste on everyone.
Don’t different people have the right to determine what is
most rewarding for them? Don’t they have the right to decide freely whether
they wish to forgo the ultimate form of sensory enjoyment because they are
seeking a different goal in life? Is eating chocolate ice cream or gazing on a
petunia more satisfying than winning a golf tournament or seeing your team win
the Super Bowl?
Keep in mind that when one person enjoys the thrill of
victory in a competitive sport, someone else must suffer the agony of
defeat.
As always, who is to decide? Who will remove all of the
vanilla ice cream from the supermarket and deprive you of a free choice between
vanilla and chocolate?
Fortunately for him, Harris does not believe in free will.
He does believe in choice, but not in the freedom to choose between vanilla and
chocolate, between a vacation in Tahiti and a vacation in Bermuda, between a
job that pays more for more hours of work and a job that pays less but offers
more time with the family.
There is no right and wrong in the world of taste. That’s
why, as the old saying goes, “there’s no arguing with taste.”
Similarly, Harris presents utilitarian arguments for
maximizing human well-being by analogizing well-being with health.
In his words:
Many
critics claim that my reliance on the concept of “well-being” is arbitrary and
philosophically indefensible. Who’s to say that well-being is important at all
or that other things aren’t far more important? How, for instance, could you
convince someone who does not value well-being that he should, in fact, value
it? And even if one could justify well-being as the true foundation for morality,
many have argued that one would need a “metric” by which it could be
measured—else there could be no such thing as moral truth in the scientific
sense.
Then he responds to his critics:
The
simplest way to see this is by analogy to medicine and the mysterious quantity
we call “health.” Let’s swap “morality” for “medicine” and “well-being” for
“health” and see how things look:
1.
There
is no scientific basis
to say that we should value health, our own or anyone else’s. (The Value
Problem)
2.
Hence,
if someone does not care about health, or cares only about his own and not
about the health of others, there is no way to argue that he is wrong from the
point of view of science. (The Persuasion Problem)
3.
Even if
we did agree to grant “health” primacy in any discussion of medicine, it is
difficult or impossible to define it with rigor. It is, therefore, impossible
to measure health scientifically. Thus, there can be no science of medicine.
(The Measurement Problem)
There
is no problem in presupposing that the worst possible misery for everyone is
bad and worth avoiding and that normative morality consists, at an absolute
minimum, in acting so as to avoid it. To say that the worst possible misery for
everyone is “bad” is, on my account, like saying that an argument that
contradicts itself is “illogical.”
But, his critics have pointed out, health is measurable and
well-being is not. Your health involves you as a biological organism. But your
well-being has a totally different basis.
Some people might believe that their well-being is enhanced
by spending their time contemplating great art. Others may prefer to go to work
manufacturing widgets. Is there a scientific basis for establishing which
contributes more to your well-being? Is there a scientific experiment that can
show which produces the ultimate form of satisfaction? What if your ultimate satisfaction lies in doing something good for someone else? If so, should we
institute government policies that “nudge” people or force people toward the
one or the other?
If one family possesses a larger house and lives in a better
neighborhood, thus granting its children more well-being than the children than
those less fortunate, should we abolish the economic system that allowed one
family to out-compete the other and to enjoy enhanced well-being?
Imagine that one country prefers to spend its time
contemplating art. Imagine that its neighboring country has chosen to spend its
time building armaments. What will prevent the latter from invading and
enslaving the former, the better to become more prosperous and at the same time
have access to the great art, too? If free will does not exist, the nation that
has lost its freedom has not lost anything of great value.
You might say that war is bad for everyone’s well-being, and
you might say the same about economic competition, but people do fight wars and
they engage in economic competition. It’s easy to imagine a society where freedom
is not allowed, where there is only one kind of ice cream and where there is no
economic competition. It’s been tried, and, by objective standards, it has
failed.
You will note that I slipped the phrase “objective standards”
into the last paragraph. Perhaps, that is where the confusion lies.
We can posit that human health and well-being have both been
enhanced by free enterprise and the Industrial Revolution.
Public health has been measurably improved by industrial
sanitation and biomedical science. Starving peoples have been fed by privatized
agriculture.
When Mao Zedong was running China, the extreme poverty rate
was over 80%-- that is, 80% of the people living on less than $1.25 a day.
After Deng Xiaoping privatized agriculture and gave farmers the freedom to
grow the crops they wanted and to enjoy the profits, the extreme poverty rate,
dropped, in 30 years, to around 14%.
It happened because people were given the freedom to pursue
what they believed was best for them and their families and their nation. You
may or may not like free will, but people who enjoy freedom—many enjoy it even
more than they enjoy chocolate ice cream—function more effectively and
efficiently than people who lack freedom.
So far, clear enough.
Also, some people and some cultures do not want to do what
they need to do to compete in the global economy, to say nothing of the
battlefield. Some people believe
that spiritual well-being trumps material well-being. They would rather work
less and spend the rest of their time in prayer or even in more decadent pursuits. Not everyone
wants the highest level of material well-being.
People should retain a freedom to choose the kind of world they
want to live in and the kind of world they want to leave to their children.
But, that is not all. If people gain well-being by
competing, in one or another of the markets that define our economy, they will
not be able to compete at their best unless they have chosen their path freely.
People who believe that they are being pushed, forced or
nudged in one direction or another will, in the interest of preserving their
pride and good character, resist. They are right to do so. But they will be
less efficient and less effective if they do so. Then they will be less
successful in the world. Less success brings lesser well-being.
Doubtless Harris would say that the level of initiative and
confidence that comes with the feeling that one has chosen one’s path freely is
an illusion. But, if the objective facts show that people who feel that they
have a free choice function more efficiently and effectively, who is Harris to
say otherwise? After all, the inhabitants of the workers’ paradise had no
choices. How well did they function?
You might work hard to support your family. You might work
hard to better the lives of your fellows. You are not going to work hard in
order to make things better for “everyone.” No one goes to the mat for an
abstraction. No one fails to discern friend from foe. No one gains as much satisfaction
working for the benefit of “everyone” as he does from enhancing the well-being
and pride of those near and dear to him.
Russell Blackford has articulated these points well:
[W]e
usually accept that people act in competition with each other, each seeking the
outcome that most benefits them and their loved ones. We don’t demand that
everyone agree to accept whatever course will maximize the well-being of
conscious creatures overall. Nothing like that is part of our ordinary idea of
what it is to behave morally.
Why,
for example, should I not prefer my own well-being, or the well-being of the
people I love, to overall, or global, well-being? If it comes to that, why
should I not prefer some other value altogether, such as the emergence of the
Ubermensch, to the maximization of global well-being?... Harris never provides
a satisfactory response to this line of thought, and I doubt that one is
possible. After all, as he acknowledges, the claim that “We should maximize the
global well-being of conscious creatures” is not an empirical finding. So what
is it? What in the world makes it true? How does it become binding on me if I
don’t accept it?
Harris concedes the point when he offers his own utopian
vision:
Consider
how we would view a situation in which all of us miraculously began to behave
so as to maximize our collective well-being. Imagine that on the basis of
remarkable breakthroughs in technology, economics, and politic skill, we create
a genuine utopia on earth. Needless to say, this wouldn’t be boring, because we
will have wisely avoided all the boring utopias. Rather, we will have created a
global civilization of astonishing creativity, security, and happiness.
Every rational individual knows that these utopian
fantasies, when put into practice, have produced anything but misery.
Loving everyone collectively and the same is impossible. A person learns to love individuals that are closest, such as family and friends.
ReplyDeleteSkip that step and a person can love no one.
Harris can think about controlling and making taste decisions for others because he does not like anybody.
Oh, but he's so much SMARTER than we, so he must be right.
ReplyDeleteChange the term "well-being" to "General Will", and -- voila! -- Harris is a modern day Jean-Jacques Rousseau. And we know how well his ideas played out!
ReplyDeleteSo bring on zee guillotine (or whatever its 21st century equivalent would be -- compulsory diversity training, perhaps?)!