Neuroscience can explain some things, but not others. Among its
more conspicuous limitations is its inability to explain moral judgment.
In effect, it’s an old story, dating to David Hume. Every
philosopher knows Hume’s argument: science can describe what is; ethics tells
us what we should do.
Science can tell you what happens when you shoot a bullet
into the wall. It can tell you what happens when you shoot a bullet into
someone’s head. It does not tell you whether you should do the one or the other.
If you are thinking that it is wrong to shoot people in the
head, what should you do when someone is coming at you with an axe?
Recently, philosopher Thomas Nagel raised these issues, and many
more, in a review of Joshua Greene’s new book: Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap between Us and Them.
Nagel is an eminent philosopher; he is emeritus at New York
University. Greene is an associate professor of psychology at Harvard.
One is tempted to call it a clash of the academic titans.
It begins with an analysis of what is called the footbridge
or trolley dilemma:
The
footbridge dilemma: A runaway trolley is headed for five railway workmen who
will be killed if it proceeds on its present course. You are standing on a
footbridge spanning the tracks, in between the oncoming trolley and the five
people. Standing next to you is a 300-pound man. The only way to save the five
people is to push him off the footbridge and onto the tracks below. The man
will die as a result, but his body will stop the trolley. (You are only half
his size and would not stop the trolley if you yourself jumped in front of it.)
The switch dilemma: A runaway trolley is
headed for five workmen who will be killed if nothing is done. You can save
these five people by hitting a switch that will turn the trolley onto a
sidetrack. Unfortunately there is a single workman on the sidetrack who will be
killed if you hit the switch.
Research has shown that more people will hit the switch than
will throw the 300-pound man on the tracks. Apparently, this demonstrates that
the brain indulges in two kinds of moral reasoning, deriving from different
neural systems.
Sometimes we use reason; sometimes we act out of emotion.
Such is the conclusion that neuroscientists have reached.
We ought to recognize that these situations are both
fictions. How does your response change when the 300 pound man is a stranger
and the people on the track are members of your family? Or, vice versa.
Shouldn’t you consider the consequences you will suffer if
you allow your five brothers to be hit be a trolley? How are you going to
explain to their families that you could have prevented it but didn't? Are you going to say that you were following a principle you learned in a college course?
And don’t the two tasks entail completely different levels
of risk? If you yourself are considerably smaller than the 300-pound man, it
might not be very easy to push him onto the tracks? If he is an offensive
lineman on a professional football team he might easily respond to your threat
by throwing you on the track. Then, six people will die.
Obviously, hitting a switch does not put you at any risk,
though questions of criminal liability will surely enter into your calculations.
Apparently, Greene believes that there is something wrong in
the way people react to the footbridge problem. By his lights and by his
utilitarian calculation we should in all cases opt for saving the most lives. That
is, we should not even calculate at the minimal level that the initial problem
suggests. We should not make risk assessments and should not, ideally,
privilege friends and family over strangers.
How long do you think the human species would have survived if everyone had thought in those terms?
Nagel responds by noting that human ethics promotes cooperation within groups but does not promote cooperation with outsiders. Ethics is based on a distinction between friend and foe or friend and stranger.
Apparently, this chagrins thinkers like Greene who believe that
since all human beings belong to one species they are equal in the most relevant
respects and should be treated as such.
If science, Greene seems to be saying, does not distinguish
between different members of the same species, we should not do so either. He
seems to be aiming at a utopia where everyone gets along, where there are no insider
and outsiders, where there are no friends and enemies.
It is worth underscoring that such a world is a pure
fiction. To denounce human beings for not living according to a fiction is to
take leave of reality.
It is irrational to do so, Nagel suggests, in the name of science.
Nagel summarizes Greene’s argument:
Greene
calls this problem the “tragedy of commonsense morality.” In a nutshell, it is
the tragedy that moralities that help members of particular communities to
cooperate peacefully do not foster a comparable harmony among members of
different communities.
Morality
evolved to enable cooperation, but this conclusion comes with an important
caveat. Biologically speaking, humans were designed for cooperation, but only with some people. Our moral
brains evolved for cooperation within
groups, and perhaps only within the context of personal relationships.
Our moral brains did not evolve for cooperation between groups(at least not all groups).... As with the evolution of
faster carnivores, competition is essential for the evolution of
cooperation….
We feel
obligations to fellow members of our community but not to outsiders. So the
solution to the tragedy of the commons has generated a new tragedy, which we
can see wherever the values and the interests of different communities
conflict, not only on an international scale but also more locally, within
pluralistic societies that contain multiple moral communities.
To
solve this problem Greene thinks we need what he calls a “metamorality,” based
on a common currency of value that all human beings can acknowledge, even if it
conflicts with some of the promptings of the intuitive moralities of common
sense.
Nagel explains that Greene’s argument derives from utilitarian
morality—the greatest good for the greatest number, regardless of who they are
and what my relationship to them is.
In Nagel’s words:
Utilitarianism,
as propounded by Bentham and Mill, is the principle that we should aim to
maximize happiness impartially, and it conflicts with the instinctive
commonsense morality of individual rights, and special heightened obligations
to those to whom one is related by blood or community. Those intuitive values
have their uses as rough guides to action in many ordinary circumstances, but
they cannot, in Greene’s view, provide the basis for universally valid
standards of conduct.
The
basic point for Greene’s purposes is that we have strong moral reactions
against certain actions that cause harm but serve the greater good on balance,
but not to other actions that produce the same balance of good and harm.
Utilitarianism,
he believes, allows us to transcend our evolutionary heritage.
The question then is whether he offers a coherent account of how and why
we should give it this authority.
Greene is asking us to overcome our human nature, to ignore
traditional ethics, and to write ourselves out of whatever groups we belong to.
If, as most people accept, humans are social beings, they
all belong to one or another group. But, it means nothing to belong to a group
if everyone belongs to the group and no one belongs to another group. Even lions have prides.
Moreover, if the bottom line sees us all as members of the
species, our membership and our status do not depend on how we behave. If biology places you in the species, nothing you can do can remove you
from it.
Call it human nature if you like, but the supposedly
scientific approach is really a disguised form of heavy idealism, the kind that
dislikes human beings as they are and rejects their way of reasoning morally. Greene wants us
to overcome our humanity and our moral nature.
Nagel writes:
This
implies something that is clearly not a fact of empirical psychology: namely,
that there are values by which we should “ideally” govern our lives, and that
they are captured by the utilitarian aim of maximizing total happiness,
counting everyone’s happiness impartially as of equal value, with no preference
for ourselves or our loved ones.
Obviously, Greene’s argument flies in the face of right
reason. Nagel explains how Greene tries to fudge the issue:
Utilitarianism,
he [Greene] contends, is not refuted by footbridge-type intuitions that
conflict with it, because those intuitions are best understood not as
perceptions of intrinsic wrongness, but as gut reactions that have evolved to
serve social peace by preventing interpersonal violence. Similar debunking
explanations can be given for other commonsense moral intuitions, such as the
obligation to favor members of one’s own group over strangers, or the stronger
obligation one feels to rescue an identified individual who is drowning in
front of you than to contribute to saving the lives of greater numbers of
anonymous victims far away. According to Greene, it is understandable in light
of evolutionary psychology that we have these intuitions, and for the most part
it does no harm to let our conduct be guided by them, but they are not
perceptions of moral truth, and they do not discredit the utilitarian
response when it tells us to do something different.
As Nagel says, Greene is telling us to be more, or perhaps
less than human:
While
we cannot get rid of our automatic settings, Greene says we should try to
transcend them—and if we do, we cannot expect the universal principles that we
adopt to “feel right.” Utilitarianism has counterintuitive consequences, but we
arrive at it by recognizing that happiness matters to everyone, and that
objectively no one matters more than anyone else, even though subjectively we
are each especially important to ourselves.
No one matters more than anyone else? Try explaining that to
your husband, your wife or your children.
Many people take Greene’s ideas seriously, but they are
perfectly unserious. He himself knows that, practically speaking, no one is
going to starve his family to feed a bunch of strangers. No one is going
to provide significantly less for his family in order to provide more for
people who he knows nothing about.
For all I know, Greenne is trying to persuade people to give up
more of their wealth in order to give it to the less fortunate. Perhaps he is
really just arguing for higher taxes on the rich.
Greene explains his point of view:
If it seems
absurd to ask real humans to abandon their families, friends, and other
passions for the betterment of anonymous strangers, then that can’t be what
utilitarianism actually asks of real humans. Trying to do this would be a
disaster, and disasters don’t maximize happiness. Humans evolved to live lives
defined by relationships with people and communities, and if our goal is to
make the world as happy as possible, we must take this defining feature of
human nature into account.
Nagel points out that Greene is:
…
accusing himself of failing to live in accordance with beliefs that he accepts,
beliefs about ideal values.
It will make more sense if we see Greene as the kind of
liberal who wants to spend more money on education and who wants all school to
be racially integrated, but who sends his own children to racially segregated private schools.
What's good for the masses is not good enough for his family.
He holds to principles in order to assert his membership,
not in the human species, but in the group of pious liberals who hold to the
right dogmas and who vote the right way.
Let’s not call it science.
Having a degree in Physics, I can't see a 300# man (or 300# of anything else) stopping a runaway trolley. The trolley by itself, w/o passengers or operator, must weigh 10000 pounds
ReplyDelete(3 4-door cars or minivans) or more, and I'd guess 15-20000. The premise is false.
"Greene calls this problem the “tragedy of commonsense morality." If Greene said that, Greene does not understand the meaning of common sense.
Ah, utilitarianism! People as interchangeable parts. Let's use Greene as the 300# man, and see how he likes it then.
Had the 300 lb man lived, he would have had a daughter who will develop a cure for a fatal disease, and save millions of lives. Since she is never born, the cure is not developed in time to save the millions that would have otherwise been saved. The scenario saves 5 present day lives, but kills millions of future lives.
ReplyDelete