Steven Pinker must count as an excellent salesman. Bright-eyed
and bushy haired, he is, as Yoram Hazony explains in the Wall Street Journal,
selling the Enlightenment. He did not write a historical analysis; he wrote a polemic. He has already seduced the world’s richest dupe,
Bill Gates, and has lured many others into his lair.
I have written about Pinker’s theses several times already.
I have also noted that British philosopher John Gray has written one of the
best critiques of his book. It turns out that, like any snake oil salesman,
Pinker has cherry picked his facts and has distorted philosophy and
intellectual history almost beyond recognition.
See my prior posts, here.
In truth, I believe that Pinker is selling Enlightenment
because he wants to restore the prestige of atheism. The twentieth century saw
the most ambitious attempts to create atheist cultures, through Communism, and,
if these efforts and the ensuing human calamities proved anything, they proved
that atheism should be relegated to the dustbin of intellectual history. And
yet, some people never learn. Among them Steven Pinker.
As I have mentioned, Pinker’s deception involves giving the
Enlightenment credit for everything good that has happened since the end of the
eighteenth century, while blaming everything bad on those who rejected it. As
has been noted, he ignores a figure like David Hume, the leading British
proponent of empirical thinking and ignores the influence that an Enlightenment
thinker like Rousseau had on the French Revolution—the first great attempt to
cleanse the culture of religious authority. How did that one work out, Steve?
Hazony presents Pinker’s case:
Boosters
of the Enlightenment make an attractive case. Science, medicine, free political
institutions, the market economy—these things have dramatically improved our
lives. They are all, Mr. Pinker writes, the result of “a process set in motion
by the Enlightenment in the late 18th century,” when philosophers “replaced
dogma, tradition and authority with reason, debate and institutions of
truth-seeking.” … So give thanks for
“thinkers like John Locke and Immanuel Kant who argued that people should stop
deferring blindly to authority” and instead “think things through from the
ground up.”
As Mr.
Pinker sums it up: “Progress is a gift of the ideals of the Enlightenment, and
will continue to the extent that we rededicate ourselves to those ideals.”
David Hume once opined that the salient question for
philosophers was: which came first, experience or ideas. You can reformulate it
to say, which comes first facts or theories. In Pinker’s Enlightenment, facts
fall to the wayside as theoretical ideals take pride of place. It’s the
difference between the detective who begins an investigation by collecting
facts and a detective who begins his investigation by concocting a theory, then
to collect only those facts that affirm the theory.
Pinker shows his limited knowledge of political philosophy
when he pretends that the American constitution was produced by Enlightenment
philosophers. Hazony explains that the sources of that great document and of
the American Republic lie elsewhere:
The
widely circulated 15th-century treatise “In Praise of the Laws of England,”
written by the jurist John Fortescue, clearly explains due process and the
theory now called “checks and balances.” The English constitution, Fortescue
wrote, establishes personal liberty and economic prosperity by shielding the
individual and his property from the government. The protections that appear in
the U.S. Bill of Rights were mostly set down in the 1600s by those drafting
England’s constitutional documents—men such as John Selden, Edward Hyde and
Matthew Hale.
He continues:
They
were religious, English nationalists and political conservatives. They were
familiar with the claim that unfettered reason should remake society, but they
rejected it in favor of developing a traditional constitution that had proved
itself. When Washington, Jay, Hamilton and Madison initiated a national
government for the U.S., they primarily turned to this conservative tradition,
adapting it to local conditions.
As for giving the Enlightenment credit for modern science
and medicine, we might note that Pinker ignored David Hume while extolling
Immanuel Kant… a man who famously derided the scientific method. Said method,
invented by Aristotle, and developed by Galileo and Francis Bacon, among
others, is not a product of the Enlightenment. Copernicus and Kepler largely
predated the Enlightenment.
At the least, the scientific method allows that experiment—that
is, experience—can disprove hypotheses. Enlightenment idealists, Hazony will
explain, derive their theories before the fact and pretend that the facts prove
them out. Their ultimate goal is to seduce or induce or force you into
believing in these theories. God help you if you do not accept the prevailing,
logically deduced orthodox beliefs.
Hazony offers this about the development of modern science:
Nor is
there much truth in the assertion that we owe modern science and medicine to
Enlightenment thought. A more serious claim of origin can be made by the Renaissance,
the period between the 15th and 17th centuries, particularly in Italy, Holland
and England. Tradition-bound English kings, for example, sponsored pathbreaking
scientific institutions such as the Royal College of Physicians, founded in
1518. One of its members, William Harvey, discovered the circulation of the
blood in the early 17th century. The Royal Society of London for Improving
Natural Knowledge, founded in 1660, was led by such men as Robert Boyle and
Isaac Newton, decisive figures in physics and chemistry. Again, these were
politically and religiously conservative figures. They knew the arguments,
later associated with the Enlightenment, for overthrowing political, moral and
religious tradition, but mostly they rejected them.
Most important is the emphasis Enlightenment philosopher put
on the power of formal logic. I discussed this at length in my book The Last Psychoanalyst. They held out
the hope and stoked the faith that a deduction of theorems from axiomatic first
principles could provide us with absolute truths… to which reality was obliged
to concord.
Hazony presents this idea:
Mr.
Pinker opens his first chapter by endorsing Kant’s declaration that only reason
allows human beings to emerge from their “self-incurred immaturity” by casting
aside the “dogmas and formulas” of authority and tradition.
For
Kant, reason is universal, infallible and a priori—meaning independent of
experience. As far as reason is concerned, there is one eternally valid,
unassailably correct answer to every question in science, morality and
politics. Man is rational only to the extent that he recognizes this and spends
his time trying to arrive at that one correct answer.
He continues to remark the colossal arrogance of this
philosophical con game:
This
astonishing arrogance is based on a powerful idea: that mathematics can produce
universal truths by beginning with self-evident premises—or, as Rene Descartes
had put it, “clear and distinct ideas”—and then proceeding by means of
infallible deductions to what Kant called “apodictic certainty.” Since this
method worked in mathematics, Descartes had insisted, it could be applied to
all other disciplines. The idea was subsequently taken up and refined by Thomas
Hobbes, Baruch Spinoza, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau as well as Kant.
And he rejects it:
It
is completely wrong. Human reason is incapable of reaching universally valid,
unassailably correct answers to the problems of science, morality and politics
by applying the methods of mathematics.
We will mention as a sidelight that Bertrand Russell and
Alfred North Whitehead proposed in an astonishing work, called the Principia Mathematica to derive all of
mathematics from the principles and precepts of formal logic. When the book
came out famed German logician Gottlob Frege wrote to them to show that they
had made a fundamental mistake… crashing their entire system.
Later Kurt Godel demonstrated that while the first order
predicate calculus was complete and consistent, the second order predicate
calculus, the one that contained numbers, was incomplete and could generate
sentences that could not be assigned a truth value.
Since science, if it is based on anything, is based on
skepticism, on the willingness not to jump to conclusions and on the understanding
that all conclusions are subject to further experimental verification or
falsification, Pinker endorses it. And yet, Kant and his followers had no use
for skepticism. They were, Hazony explains, post medieval dogmatists:
Mr.
Pinker praises skepticism as a cornerstone of the Enlightenment’s “paradigm of
how to achieve reliable knowledge.” But the principal figures of Enlightenment
philosophy weren’t skeptics. Just the opposite: Their aim was to create their
own system of universal, certain truths, and in that pursuit they were as rigid
as the most dogmatic medievals.
He continues:
American
and British elites, once committed to a blend of tradition and skepticism, now
clamor for Enlightenment. They insist that they have attained universal
certainties. They display contempt worthy of Kant himself toward those who
decline to embrace their dogmas—branding them “unenlightened,” “immature,”
“illiberal,” “backward-looking,” “deplorable” and worse.
Anyway, Hazony notes that important eighteenth century
British thinkers—the kind that Pinker ignores— were skeptical of the
idealist project:
These
figures included more conservative thinkers such as David Hume, Adam Smith and
Edmund Burke. They emphasized the unreliability of “abstract reasoning,” which
they believed could end up justifying virtually any idea, no matter how
disconnected from reality, as long as it sounded self-evidently true to
someone.
As mentioned in this blog, Enlightenment philosophy, brought
into France from Germany by Rousseau gave us the French Revolution, the Reign
of Terror and Napoleon. Hazony continues:
Imported
into France by Rousseau, it quickly pulled down the monarchy and the state,
producing a series of failed constitutions, the Reign of Terror and finally the
Napoleonic Wars—all in the name of infallible and universal reason. Millions
died as Napoleon’s armies sought to destroy and rebuild every government in
Europe in accordance with the one correct political theory allowed by
Enlightenment philosophy. Yet Napoleon was simply trying, in Mr. Brooks’s
phrase, to “think things through from the ground up.”
You would almost tax Pinker with dishonesty, with playing with
loaded dice, in his presentation of these great Enlightenment historical
events. In Hazony’s words:
Mr.
Pinker’s 450-page book doesn’t mention the French Revolution. Mr. Pinker cites
Napoleon as an “exponent of martial glory” but says nothing about his launching
a universal war in the name of reason. These writers also tend to pass over
Karl Marx’s debt to the Enlightenment. Marx saw himself as promoting universal
reason, extending the work of the French Revolution by insisting that the
workers of the world stop (again in Mr. Brooks’s words) “deferring blindly to
authority.” The “science” Marx developed “from the ground up” killed tens of
millions in the 20th century.
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteIt does look like a good challenging essay, including challenging reason itself:
ReplyDeleteHazony: "Human reason is incapable of reaching universally valid, unassailably correct answers to the problems of science, morality and politics by applying the methods of mathematics."
And conclusion: "You can’t have both Enlightenment and skepticism. You have to choose."
So skepticism is a conservative stance, and science is as well, where knowledge is always provisional. I'd summarize the problem is "motivated reasoning" blinds us, even if scientific collaboration can help reduce this.