I cannot imagine a better reviewer for Steven Pinker's latest treatise on the Enlightenment than cantankerous British philosopher John Gray. When it comes to reading Pinker’s 576 page tome, better him than me.
Gray is well suited to the task because he is not, to say
the least, a wild-eyed optimist. We count on him to provide a counterweight
to Pinker’s imitation of Dr. Pangloss. Where Pinker looks at glass that is half
full and declares it to be full, Gray sees the emptiness within. He holds a tragic view of human existence,
one that correlates reasonably well with Freud’s, but not with mine.
Such is life.
Yet, Gray is a philosopher. Pinker is a psychologist. And
Gray has a far better grasp of intellectual history than Pinker. Thus, you
expect that he will do more than throw shade at the naïve young Pinker. And,
Gray is not intimidated because the world’s richest dupe, Bill Gates,
said that Pinker’s book is the best book he has ever read.
Gray concludes his review thusly:
Judged
as a contribution to thought, Enlightenment Now is
embarrassingly feeble. With its primitive scientism and manga-style history of
ideas, the book is a parody of Enlightenment thinking at its crudest. A more
intellectually inquiring author would have conveyed something of the
Enlightenment’s richness and diversity. Yet even if Pinker was capable of
providing it, intellectual inquiry is not what his anxious flock demands. Only
an anodyne, mythical Enlightenment can give them what they crave, which is
relief from painful doubt.
Given
this overriding emotional imperative, presenting them with the actual,
conflict-ridden, often illiberal Enlightenment would be – by definition, one
might say – unreasonable. Judged as a therapeutic manual for rattled
rationalists, Enlightenment Now is
a highly topical and much-needed book. In the end, after all, reason is only
the slave of the passions.
Liberals are drooling over Pinker because his book provides
them with much needed therapy. The liberal order, the hope for liberal
democracy has been losing ground lately. Now, Pinker has come along to soothe those hurt feelings, to calm those dashed hopes, with an assurance that
liberals are on the right side of history.
So says Gray in his opening paragraph:
To
think of this book as any kind of scholarly exercise is a category mistake. The
purpose of Pinker’s laborious work is to reassure liberals that they are on
“the right side of history”.
This tells us that Pinker is trafficking in born-again
Hegelianism… the kind of philosophy that sees history unfolding according to a
predetermined plan, and reaching a predetermined goal, no matter what you or I
do or say. If you think that history is going to bail out your theoretical errors,
you are seriously mistaken.
Pinker might have noticed that true Hegelians, like Karl
Marx and Vladimir Lenin, do not believe in freedom. They do not believe in free
market capitalism. They hold it to be a monstrosity
concocted to oppress the masses and to delay the arrival of the Worker’s
Paradise. And yet, Gray points out that Pinker loves capitalism and free
enterprise, grand accomplishments of what he sees as the Enlightenment.
One understands that Francis Fukuyama has already explained
that the endpoint of the Hegelian World Spirit’s movement is a liberal
democracy. And one understands that Hegel himself saw the apotheosis of the
World Spirit in the conquering armies of Napoleon. Both Hegel and Fukuyama
thought that Napoleon was bringing the liberal democracy promoted by
the French Revolution.
And yet, the French Revolution and the Reign of Terror were not promoting liberal
democracy. They were certainly not promoting free enterprise. The latter was a
product of the British, i.e. Scottish Enlightenment, through David Hume and Adam Smith. Hume, the most important British Enlightenment thinker
is, Gray tells us, ignored by Pinker. Doubtless Hume’s empirical bent was
inconsistent with Pinker’s Hegelian idealism.
The true logical outcome of the Hegelian dialectic is a police state, where the power of the state imposes correct thinking on the masses. Its not a marketplace of ideas, but One Mind, thinking the same thoughts and believing the same beliefs.
Worse yet, for a Pinker, who rejects religion and faith,
without really understanding either, is that free enterprise
bases its concept of freedom on the free will that has been central to Western
religion since the book of Genesis. Pinker’s belief in free enterprise shows
that he does not understand the difference between the Franco-German
Enlightenment and its British cousin.
The difference should be clear to everyone, especially since
I related it in my book The Last Psychoanalyst. In a world where people possess
true freedom they are not trapped within a grand historical narrative. They are not worrying their souls about whether they are onthe right side of history. They are
involved in a game where the outcome is uncertain. They participate in the
market as players making moves in a game. To imagine that it will all work
itself out no matter what you do is naïve.
Gray taxes Pinker with simpleminded thinking, as in this
explanation of the Pinker argument about reason and faith:
Early
on in this monumental apologia for a currently fashionable version of
Enlightenment thinking, he writes: “To take something on faith means to believe
it without good reason, so by definition a faith in the existence of
supernatural entities clashes with reason.” Well, it’s good to have that
settled once and for all. There is no need to trouble yourself with the
arguments of historians, anthropologists and evolutionary biologists, who treat
religion as a highly complex phenomenon, serving a variety of human needs. All
you need do is consult a dictionary, and you will find that religion is – by
definition – irrational.
If I may, as I have often remarked, the great Thomas Aquinas
showed over the course of thousands of pages that faith can indeed be rational.
As for the question of supernatural entities, I will introduce a point once argued by Jacques
Lacan, with an assist from Alexander Meiklejohn. Namely, how do you know that
ideas exist? You have never seen, heard, tasted, touched or smelled an idea. You
will accept that the orbit of the planets, as rendered in a formula by Kepler,
obeys a law, thus an idea. If so, the idea certainly existed before Kepler
wrote it down as a scientific law. If it existed, where was it? And, what mind was thinking it?
You might happily dismiss religious faith, but if you
undertake a project or implement a new policy, you do not know whether or not
it will work. You will proceed on the basis of a faith that it will… even if
there are no scientific facts about the outcome.
Gray is too kind to mention it, but Pinker has ignored a
basic insight offered by David Hume—namely, that science is
about what "is" while ethics is about “should.” This means that you cannot use
science to articulate ethical principles. Those who do, Gray notes, are not
practicing science, but are indulging in scientism.
For
Pinker, the second law of thermodynamics doesn’t simply identify a universal
regularity in the natural world, “it defines the fate of the universe and the
ultimate purpose of life, mind, and human striving: to deploy energy and
knowledge to fight back the tide of entropy and carve out refuges of beneficial
order”.
Leaving the physics to the side, this suggests that life is
a zero-sum game, that one person’s economic progress must come at the expense
of someone else… and thus, that we must redistribute wealth rather than to grow
it. Again, without saying anything about Newton, making his laws of
thermodynamics into moral principles causes problems.
As for Newton’s third law of thermodynamics—“for every
action there is an equal and opposite reaction”—if you should be tempted to
make it into a moral principle, you will find yourself with something like the
law of the talion: an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth. And you will note
that this principle of retaliatory justice has largely been superseded by the
Golden Rule—do unto others as you would have them do unto you. Again,
disregarding the physics, the law of the talion produces social disharmony, an unending cycle of violence.
As I have suggested, and as Gray argues, Pinker is presenting
a polemic. This does not involve the scientific method where facts can prove or
disprove a hypothesis. Pinker has produced a fictional world where the Enlightenment is
responsible for all the good that has happened in the world, and where those who
reject the Enlightenment have produced all the evil. It is both childishly naïve and Hegelian:
To be
sure, for Pinker there are no bad Enlightenment ideas. One of the features of
the comic-book history of the Enlightenment he presents is that it is innocent
of all evil. Accordingly, when despots such as Lenin repeatedly asserted that
they engaged in mass killing in order to realise an Enlightenment project – in
Lenin’s case, a more far-reaching version of the Jacobin project of
re-educating society by the methodical use of terror – they must have been
deluded or lying.
And also,
Pinker
stipulates that the Enlightenment, by definition, is intrinsically liberal.
Modern tyrannies must therefore be products of counter-Enlightenment ideologies
– Romanticism, nationalism and the like. Enabling liberals to avoid asking
difficult questions about why their values are in retreat, this is a popular
view. Assessed in terms of historical evidence, it is also a myth.
For Pinker, all the horrors that have befallen the human
species since the advent of the Enlightenment flow from the pen of one
Friedrich Nietzsche. Better to blame it on Nietzsche than accepting that the German Enlightenment produced both Communism and Naziism.
In his words:
If one
wanted to single out a thinker who represented the opposite of humanism (indeed
of pretty much every argument in this book) one couldn’t do better than the
German philologist Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche helped to inspire the
romantic militarism that led to the First World War and the fascism that led to
the Second. The connections between Nietzsche’s ideas and the megadeath movements
of the 20th century are obvious enough; a glorification of violence and power,
an eagerness to raze the institutions of liberal democracy, a contempt for most
of humanity, and a stone-hearted indifference to human life.
Gray takes Pinker to school on his straw man version of Nietzsche:
A
lifelong admirer of Voltaire, Nietzsche was a critic of the Enlightenment
because he belonged in it. Far from being an enemy of humanism, he promoted
humanism in the most radical form. In future, humankind would fashion its
values and shape its destiny by its own unfettered will. True, he conferred
this privilege only on a select few.
He
recognised no principle of human equality. But where does concern with equality
come from? Not from science, which can be used to promote many values. As
Nietzsche never tired of pointing out, the ideal of equality is an inheritance
from Judaism and Christianity. His hatred of equality is one reason he was such
a vehement atheist.
Truth be told, Nietzsche was an Enlightenment thinker. He
was also an enemy of Judaism and Christianity. And he was “a vehement atheist.”
From Pinker’s perspective, he has everything that anyone would want. Except perhaps the proper quantity of empathy. But, to be fair, Paul Bloom has argued that empathy is not necessarily morally benevolent. It can make you into a sadistic sociopath.
Nietzsche rejected the civilizing values bestowed by
religion and wanted human beings to reconstruct their value system based on a
liberated will. An aspect of human being, welling up from within the organism, the will should set forth new rules that everyone will be obliged to live with. As happens
with all forms of Platonist thinking, a select few will be the arbiters of
these rules.
Gray sees the Pinker book as a pep talk for wavering
liberals:
Enlightenment Now is
a rationalist sermon delivered to a congregation of wavering souls. To think of
the book as any kind of scholarly exercise is a category mistake. Much of its
more than 500 pages consists of figures aiming to show the progress that has
been made under the aegis of Enlightenment ideals. Of course, these figures
settle nothing. Like Pinker’s celebrated assertion that the world is becoming
ever more peaceful – the statistical basis of which has been demolished by
Nassim Nicholas Taleb – everything depends on what is included in them and how
they are interpreted.
Gray concludes on a sober note, one that echoes views
presented on this blog:
If an
Enlightenment project survives, what reason is there for thinking it will be
embodied in liberal democracy? What if the Enlightenment’s future is not in the
liberal West, now almost ungovernable as a result of the culture wars in which
it is mired, but Xi Jinping’s China, where an altogether tougher breed of
rationalist is in charge? It is a prospect that Voltaire, Jeremy Bentham and
other exponents of enlightened despotism would have heartily welcomed.