For many years now I have been making the case against
empathy on this blog. See also and especially my book, The
Last Psychoanalyst. In particular, I have been saying that therapists who proclaim
empathy to be the ultimate emotional virtue have misled us.
These therapists have reasoned that since psychopaths
conspicuously lack empathy, they would cease to be psychopaths if only they
could be taught to feel the pain they were inflicting on their victims. Thus
did empathy become the panacea for the evils that humans do. It’s a nice idea,
unless the same psychopaths like to feel a bit of pain now and then.
Therapists also imagine that empathy works like an emotional
glue that produces profound human connections. They see it connecting people at
the most profound level. Better to be connected by sharing feelings, they say,
than by participating in the same ritual or discussing the same objective
reality, like the weather.
For my part, I have noted that if you are involved in
competition, empathy for the pain you will want to inflict on your opponent will
not make you a more fierce competitor. In fact, it will dull your competitive
edge.
Happily, I am not alone in thinking that empathy is not all
that it is knocked up to be. Yale psychologist Paul Bloom has done very interesting
work on the topic.
Recently, in The Atlantic Bloom argued that people who
have a superior capacity for empathy are often willing to inflict the greatest
pain on those they believe deserve it. Given the right circumstances, empaths
happily allow themselves to be carried away with an impulse to take revenge.
It is a fascinating observation. And yet, for all I know,
the reason could be that people who believe in feelings are most likely to lack
a rational or socio-ethical check on their feelings. They are most likely to allow
themselves to be led around by their feelings. Yet, Bloom is certainly correct to argue that empathy does
not, in and of itself, function as an unalloyed moral virtue.
Speaking of moral sentiments, Bloom presents Adam Smith’s
version of this idea, surely one of the earliest observations:
In The Theory of Moral Sentiments,
published in 1759, Adam Smith observes that when we see someone harmed by
another, we feed off his desire for vengeance: “We are rejoiced to see him
attack his adversary in his turn, and eager and ready to assist him.” Even if
he dies, our imagination does the trick: “We enter, as it were, into his body,
and in our imaginations, in some measure, animate anew the deformed and mangled
carcass of the slain, [and] bring home in this manner his case to our bosoms.”
People with a superior capacity for
empathy tend to indulge in sadistic behaviors. At times, they do so in the name
of justice, but in other times, the motives are more complex.
Students were asked to choose how much hot sauce to give to
two people, both of whom are in financial difficulty. One of the subjects was
non-plussed by her financial problems while the other was anxious about hers.
When given the choice, the students who rated highest in empathy gave more hot
sauce to the woman who was more worried about her condition:
Bloom explains:
… the
subjects chose to give more hot sauce to this other person when the student was
described as distressed. Their empathy drove aggression, even when it made no
moral sense.
One takes Bloom’s point, but perhaps the students believed
that the whinier of the two women was more in need of a wake-up call. No one
likes a whiner. The woman was not going to work her way out of a financial situation by wallowing in self-pity or worry.
If an empath is more sensitive to the whiner’s pain, he
might resent her for inviting him to share it. Thus, he might want to give her more
hot sauce in order to tell her to suck it up and act like an adult. I have not
read the study, but I wonder whether the students would have acted differently
if the impecunious subjects were male.
Of course, the impecunious women had not done anything wrong. So, I
am not yet convinced that this experiment exists on the same continuum as the
ones that ask empaths how they would respect to news of a terrorist atrocity or
to stories about domestic abuse.
According to Bloom, those who are most empathetic are most likely to
fprescribe the harshest punishment.
In Bloom’s words:
We
start by giving people a simple test that measures their degree of empathy.
Then we tell them some awful stories, about journalists kidnapped in the Middle
East, about child abuse in the United States. And then we ask them how best to
respond to those responsible for the suffering. In the Middle East case, we
give a continuum of political options, from doing nothing to public criticism,
all the way to a military ground invasion. For the domestic version, we ask
about increased penalties for the abuser, from increasing their bail to making
them eligible for the death penalty. Just as with the genetic study, we found
that the more empathic people are, the more they want a harsher punishment.
It might be the case that those who have empathy are more
likely to go with their gut and less inclined to engage in the ratiocination
that would be required before choosing among different approaches.
If they identify themselves through their feelings, and take
pride in their empathy, shining the light of reason on the situation would
compromise their identity as empathetic individuals.
Keep in mind, it’s not just the outrage that counts here; it’s
the way the empaths want to express the outrage. For all I know they have been
taught by therapy to express their feelings, openly, honestly and shamelessly.
Bloom writes:
The
benefits of war—including avenging those who have suffered—are made vivid, but
the costs of war remain abstract and statistical. We see this same bias
reflected in our criminal-justice system. The outrage that comes from empathy
drives some of our most powerful punitive desires. It’s not an accident that so
many statutes are named for dead girls—as in Megan’s Law, Jessica’s Law, and
Caylee’s Law—and no surprise that there is now enthusiasm for “Kate’s Law.” The
high incarceration rate in the United States, and our continued enthusiasm for
the death penalty, is in part the product of fear and anger, but is also driven
by the consumption of detailed stories of victims’ suffering.
Here, a few questions arise. True enough, our nation has
gotten the idea that wars—especially without full mobilization-- are painless,
that they only cost us money. But then, what other than a violent military action would have been the appropriate response to the
attack on the World Trade Center. Serious countries do not allow their major
cities to be half-destroyed with impunity.
Perhaps there were other, more intelligent, equally violent
ways of responding. Yet, I find I difficult to believe that we invaded
Afghanistan because of our enhanced capacity for empathy. Were we not motivated by a moral
duty to protect the homeland and to punish those who violated it?
As for whether the costs of war are “abstract and
statistical,” it depends. In some European countries, the costs of World War I
were neither abstract nor statistical. In France, for example, the real cost—in
human life-- of WW I caused the nation to be unprepared for a German attack.
The alternative was surrender and collaboration with Nazi Germany.
I am not so sure that the nation is all that enthusiastic
about the death penalty. Nineteen states do not allow it. But, to Bloom’s point,
many of those who oppose the death penalty argue that lifetime imprisonment
without the possibility of parole is more painful than the death penalty. This supports the idea that empaths have a strong sadistic side.
On the other hand, when evaluating the popularity of incarceration,
one would need to ask oneself whether it produces a lower crime rate. If
more incarceration means less crime, then perhaps it is a rational choice.
Be that as it may, when victims are involved, empaths are
more likely to be sadistic, thus they are more likely to live by the law of the
talion—an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth.
2 comments:
Dark Eros is a book with the premise that normal social life is sadomasochistic. The desire to punish a person who is anxious is probably a very common expression of sadomasochism, however, there are persons who have no desire to punish the anxious person. Which one has more empathy? If all actions are assumed to be motivated by empathy then the question has no meaningful answer. There is a difference between having a feeling, an impulse to act, and acting on those feelings and impulses.
To me this makes me consisder how often words fail to convey accurate meaning.
We know a lack of empathy is socially destructive, but we also know abstract (liberal?) empathy for "the whole human race" is largely imaginative, and quickly evaporates in the face of a wide world whose needs will always exceed personal sanity, unless you happen to be a religious leader whose job it is to do the impossible, apparently through the holy spirit's infinite love that can be experienced through surrendering the immature parts of your ego and will to a higher will.
But back to empathy, we have attempts to differentiate its aspects, like Simon Baron-Cohen's theory that sees two ways of seeing the world, and two types of empathy, affective (emotional) and cognitive, with sociopaths retain cognitive empathy with the ability to use empathy to manipulate while the autistic are weak in cognitive empathy, possibly from failed mirror neurons.
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empathizing-systemizing_theory
And similarly Daniel Goleman quotes Paul Ekman who sees 3 kinds: cognitive, emotional and compassionate.
http://www.danielgoleman.info/three-kinds-of-empathy-cognitive-emotional-compassionate/
------
The first is “cognitive empathy,” simply knowing how the other person feels and what they might be thinking. Sometimes called perspective-taking, this kind of empathy can help in, say, a negotiation or in motivating people.
...
Then, Paul told me, there’s “emotional empathy,” – when you feel physically along with the other person, as though their emotions were contagious. This emotional contagion, social neuroscience tells us, depends in large part on the mirror neuron system. Emotional empathy makes someone well-attuned to another person’s inner emotional world, a plus in any of a wide range of callings, from sales to nursing – let alone for any parent or lover.
...
Finally, there’s what Paul calls “compassionate empathy,” which I’ve written about using the term “empathic concern”. With this kind of empathy we not only understand a person’s predicament and feel with them, but are spontaneously moved to help, if needed.
-----------
But none of this touches the other questions of darker empathy, apparently "emotional empathy", which has an ingroup bias, which sees people within one's identified tribe as more human, or being willing to "see how others see", but only those whom we wish to associate with. And this is a double bias, so it makes us feel bad if we have conflict with our ingroup, starting as children dependent upon parents, and so we can disassociate from awareness of what we dislike from those who can abandon us, including peer groups for instance. And the scapegoat mechanism is also a part of this.
But even that doesn't explain why we're willing to most hurt those closest to us, why the greatest contempt may be felt towards those we love, or those whom we once loved, and who betrayed us. So we might call all of this related to empathy, sadistic empathy perhaps, but it seems to me to not call it empathy's responsibility, even if empathy, or cognitive empathy specifically, allows us to know the greatest ways to hurt someone else?
But perhaps most of all what it seems Stuart is saying is that many people wrongly trust emotions as giving them accurate objective information about the world, and its very easy to accept that assumption is flat wrong, at least when it's someone else's emotions that are "making them" act irrationally.
Or as my men's group talked about an awareness wheel: (1) Observation (2) Evaluation (3) Feeling (4) Action. If you can separate observation from evaluation you're half way there from disarming feelings that are based on things that are not true.
Or like the quote, attributed to Mark Twain:
"It ain't what you don't know that gets you into trouble. It's what you know for sure that just ain't so."
Post a Comment