Thanks to Steven Pinker we are all having a national
conversation about the Enlightenment. We are being persuaded that replacing
religious dogma with reason was just the thing that Western Civilization needed…
to awaken from its slumber and become dynamic and democratic.
I have already offered extensive commentary on Pinker’s
errors. I will not repeat it all here. I am not alone in pointing out that
Pinker does not understand the Enlightenment and that his efforts to promote
atheism defy belief. After all, many nations around the world tried to overthrow
religion and to replace it with cultures based on atheism. They called it Communism, and even fascism. They failed miserably. If Pinker et al. wanted to
engage their rational faculties on the question of what atheism has done for
us, they would show some honesty and consider that the efforts to create
atheistic cultures have consistently failed… catastrophically so.
To be fair, Pinker and his fellow atheists will never accept
that Stalin and Mao enacted the atheist agenda. And yet, discarding
experimental results that do not fulfill the terms of your ideology does not
bespeak science or rationality. It exposes the project as a polemical exercise
designed to persuade people to believe something that makes no sense.
Of course, the defenders of atheism will quickly retort that
Communism failed because it did not affirm the basic Enlightenment value of
empathy. You see, to Enlightened thinkers and to most of our therapy culture,
empathy is the basis for all human morality. Feeling someone else’s feelings
makes you kind and gentle. Better yet, said capacity for empathy is hard-wired
in the organism. If you lack it you are a perverted psychopath… and not an
embodiment of Enlightenment values.
As it happens, this is all wrong. Serious Enlightenment
thinkers knew better than to believe that we could generate moral principles through neuroscience or any form of science.
David Hume, a leading figure in the British Enlightenment,
ignored by Pinker, famously asserted that science is about “is” while ethics is
about “should.” You cannot get from the one to the other. Naturally, our new
atheists ignore Hume… because his inconvenient thought would sink their
project.
I offer this background as an introduction to an essay
written by one M. M. Owen about famed British novelist and new atheist Ian
McEwan. I have not read McEwan, certainly a more-than-capable novelist, for
some time, so will refrain from commenting on Owen’s analysis of his fiction.
If Owen is correct and McEwan is trying to sell his enlightened atheism in his
fiction, this would count against him.
Art ought not to be preaching to us. It ought not to be
telling us what to think or what to do. If I may, art dramatizes moral
dilemmas. It shows possible outcomes. It shows possible approaches to the
problems. It is an adjunct to religious texts, but does not destroy them.
Examine Owen’s opening gambit:
Three
hundred years ago, reading novels (as opposed to the classics, or Shakespeare)
was widely seen as vulgar, indicative of a deficient mind. So was not believing
in a divine creator. Today, at least among the sort of people who tend to read
literary magazines, both these thing are more likely to be regarded as signs of
intellectual and moral refinement. For the critic James Wood, this is no
coincidence: the novel is “the slayer of religions,” a form that swept away
Biblical certitudes and replaced them with fictional narratives that move “in
the shadow of doubt,” asking readers for a belief that is fundamentally and
irreligiously metaphorical.
He continues:
One
author who would agree wholeheartedly with Wood is England’s Ian McEwan, who
asserted in 2013 that the novel is a product of the Enlightenment that “has
always been a secular and skeptical form.” McEwan is a committed nonbeliever,
so committed that he qualifies as a junior member of the intellectual
movement-cum-publishing-ploy known as New Atheism, which emerged in the wake of
9/11.
Religious texts contain stories. But they propose to set
down a series of moral principles and rules for conducting life in community.
Religion—the word means, in its Latin root: to bind together—teaches you the
rules that will allow yourself to conduct yourself as a functioning member of a social group. To teach those rules, it offers dramatic instances-- call
them parables, if you like-- that show the rules in action.
Since you cannot
have a community unless everyone is playing by the same rules, religion must
present an authority that is beyond that of a mere mortal. It may be communicated
through Moses taking dictation from God or through Jesus Christ, as Son of God,
but everyday human beings accept and follow the rules that define a culture
because they believe that these rules were laid down by a higher authority,
that is, that they were not invented to advantage or disadvantage any group of
human beings or any individual human being.
Since the new atheists seem to have no use for such rules,
they want to replace them all with empathy. And they imagine that novels teach
people to feel empathy for other people. One notes, because one is something of
a curmudgeon, that novels contain literary characters, even fictional
characters, and if the best you can do is to pretend that people learn how to
feel for their other humans by imagining that fictional characters are human,
you have a problem.
The new atheists notwithstanding, novels create alternative
worlds, what the philosophers call possible worlds. They show characters whose
actions fulfill the terms of a narrative… according to the narrative’s internal logic. They might resemble human beings, but their actions are
governed by the narrative and are shown to produce an inevitable outcome. If
people are playing a game, and not pretending to be fictional characters, the
outcome of their actions is not predetermined. Whatever moves you make in a
game, however you move the pieces on the chessboard, you are not creating a
fiction. You are playing a game. YOu are not living a narrative fiction.
Owen explains McEwan’s misguided journey into philosophy:
McEwan
aligns strongly with the New Atheism through his celebration and exaltation of
capital-R Reason. In the New Atheist framing, post-Enlightenment science
embodies the apogee of the human capacity for reason, while religion
constitutes a troublesome soup of everything that is unreason. McEwan’s literary vocation
coalesces with his scientific rationalism via the moral role he proclaims for
the novel—a role he frames in explicitly neuroscientific terms. As he describes
it, “we are innately moral beings, at the most basic, wired-in neurological
level.” This morality stems from the fact that “our imagination permits us to
understand what it is like to be someone else” (psychologists call this Theory
of Mind). From this, McEwan says, it follows that fiction is “a deeply moral
form, in that it is the perfect medium for entering the mind of another.”
He continues:
Within
the history of English letters, McEwan’s vision of the novel as a “deeply moral
form” and force for social good recalls George Eliot and Iris Murdoch—with the
special quality of its being underpinned and animated by all the things
contemporary rationalists and atheists love: evolution, neuroscience and a
morality rooted in our selfish genes, rather than in God. To listen to only
McEwan’s interviews, it all seems very straightforward: novels make us nicer
people. Good novels can ultimately achieve the same thing as antibiotics,
vaccines, nitrogen fertilizer or any other other scientific success—they can
aid the species.
The issue is going to be: are we naturally moral beings and
do we merely need to overthrow religion in order to allow our own neurons to
lead us to do the right thing. By this reasoning, the right thing will feel
good while the wrong thing will feel bad.
Aside from the fact that David Hume would have laughed as
such pretension, the truth is that, to take an obvious example, we are all born
with the capacity to learn language. And yet, unless someone teaches us
language… by talking to us… we will never speak a word. A capacity is one
thing. The rules are something else. We are not born with brains filled with
moral rules, any more than our neurons contain words and phrases.
And of course, the new atheists tell us that we just need empathy. One might respond
that we really need to learn how to get along with other people, to function
within groups, to form social organizations. Empathy might contribute to that
function, but, in any of itself, it will not give us the rules and principles
that we must all follow if we are to function within a social organization.
Owen continues:
Around
this time, he also begins to be explicit about his moral conception of the
novel: Homo sapiens are
primates that, over millennia, evolved deep-set pro-social features, including
the capacity for empathy. Empathy is fundamentally an act of imagination
(we imagine our way
into the mind of another), and an act of imagination on the scale of a good
novel can send a tsunami of it washing through the brain. Novel-reading (and
writing) can be a form of moral education.
As it happens, and as we have known since the time of the
Enlightenment, empathy is not intrinsically moral. It can promote sadism and
psychopathy. In his Theory of Moral
Sentiments Adam Smith-- another great Enlightenment thinker-- argued persuasively that if we see someone getting
beaten up, and if we put ourselves in his shoes, via imagination, and choose to
avenge the mistreatment he has received. And to avenge him against whomever comes along. Yale professor Paul Bloom argued the point in his book, Against Empathy. Empathy can make you a very nasty piece of work.
5 comments:
Pretend-people are wonderful exemplars of morality. And religion. Ummmmmmmm-hmmmmmmmmmm!
Our streets need repaving and no one has the empathy to do it. We need to hand out novels to the city and get stuff done around here.
Empathy.....there's an interesting passage in Remarque's excellent but neglected novel The Road Back.
The First World War has ended, and the protagonist, Ernst, is making his way home. On the way, he passes a gas hospital...fellow German soldiers, bad cases who cannot be moved. They have not long to live.
Ernst cannot reconcile the joy that he feels at his own imminent return home with the pain and despair he has just observed: "It is peace, yet they must die. But I, I am trembling with joy and am not ashamed--and that is odd.
Because none can wholly feel what another suffers--is that the reason why wars perpetually recur?"
When I first read this passage, I thought the Ernst's answer was incomplete, and I still think so. Actually, misdirected empathy (misdirected altruism, in Koestler's formulation) probably has as much to do with the origin of wars as does inability to feel what others suffer.
Empathy is hardly sufficient - after all, a sadist feels your pain: and enjoys it!
Are you advocating on behalf of any and all religions as a better thing that atheism or are you endorsing a specific few or one in particular?
Post a Comment