Gary Greenberg is not a psychiatrist. He has no degrees in
biochemistry or psychopharmacology and does not write prescriptions for psychiatric medication. Anne
Harrington is not a psychiatrist. She has no degrees in biochemistry or psychopharmacology and does
not write prescriptions for psychiatric medication. Whereas Greenberg is a
practicing psychologist, Harrington is a Harvard professor, one whose expertise
lies in the history of science. We are interested to read Greenberg’s review of
Harrington’s new book, being a systematic take-down of psychiatry’s
pretensions, but we note, from the top that one thing is missing.
Speaking as a non-psychiatrist with no degrees in
biochemistry or psychopharmacology, I would point out that Harrington's book-- and Greenberg's review-- seems to ignore the fact that
today’s psychiatric medication is a vast improvement over yesterday’s.
While psychiatric drugs have consistently been oversold and while their proponents
have trafficked in outlandish promises, the truth is that a schizophrenic today
has far better treatment options than did one
a century ago. The same applies to depression. People who worked in
psychiatric clinics before the advent of neuroleptics and tricyclic
anti-depressants will tell you that these medications were life saving.
Today, many psychoses are considered brain diseases,
while conditions involving most depressions and anxiety disorders are not. That
the psychiatric profession has worked long and hard to pretend that the latter
are of the same class as the former, being conditions of the brain and not the
mind, does it no honor.
On the other hand Harrington is certainly correct to see
that psychiatry is a lost soul trying to latch on to the prestige we grant to
medical practice. Psychiatrists want to be considered to be scientists. They
want us to recognize their diagnoses and nostrums as medical treatments, on the
same level as infections and antibiotics.
And yet, every time psychiatry discovers a new treatment,
whether neuroleptic drugs, lithium, SSRIs… it suddenly imagines that every
psychiatric patient suffers from the conditions that these pills treat.
Overprescription of psychiatric medication is not just a problem. It indicts
the profession and makes it look like less than science.
Greenberg summarizes Harrington’s thesis:
From
ice baths to Prozac, each development Harrington describes was touted by its
originators and adherents as the next great thing—and not without reason. Some
people really did emerge from an insulin coma without their delusions; some
people really are roused from profound and disabling depressions by a round of
electroconvulsive therapy or by antidepressant drugs. But in every case, the
treatment came first, often by accident, and the explanation never came at all.
The pathological basis of almost all mental disorders remains as unknown today
as it was in 1886—unsurprising, given that the brain turns out to be one of the
most complex objects in the universe. Even as psychiatrists prescribe a
widening variety of treatments, none of them can say exactly why any of these
biological therapies work.
Of course, if the treatments were really effective, we would
not be worrying about why they work. The problem lies in the failure to distinguish
between mental illness, a contradiction in terms, and physiological illness. It
has led to promiscuous over-prescribing of each new medication:
It
follows that psychiatrists also cannot precisely predict for whom and under
what conditions their treatments will work. That is why antipsychotic drugs are
routinely prescribed to depressed people, for example, and antidepressants to
people with anxiety disorders. Psychiatry remains an empirical discipline, its
practitioners as dependent on their (and their colleagues’) experience to
figure out what will be effective as Pliny Earle and his colleagues were.
Little wonder that the history of such a field—reliant on the authority of
scientific medicine even in the absence of scientific findings—is a record not
only of promise and setback, but of hubris.
Once upon a time, and it was not very long ago,
psychiatrists discovered the mental imbalance theory of depression. People
glommed on to this theory because it was a counterargument to the notion that
depression had a moral basis and that people who were depressed were suffering
from the sin of sloth. To be clear, there are many different kinds of
depression. The depression suffered by someone with bipolar disorder differs
from the depression suffered from someone who feels discouraged, downcast and
beaten. To the best of my knowledge good medical treatments exist for bipolar
disorder. And, SSRIs, while certainly not the panacea that their proponents
pretended them to be, have produced some good clinical outcomes for some
patients. That does not mean that these pills can or should be prescribed for everyone who complains.
As for the biology of mental illness, we should also note that physical exercise has been shown to be one of the best treatments for mental illness. Thinking that we can easily separate mind from body seems to be questionable.
Greenberg explains Harrington’s view:
The
need to dispel widespread public doubt haunts another debacle that Harrington
chronicles: the rise of the “chemical
imbalance” theory of mental illness, especially depression. The idea was
first advanced in the early 1950s, after scientists demonstrated the principles
of chemical neurotransmission; it was supported by the discovery that
consciousness-altering drugs such as LSD targeted serotonin and other
neurotransmitters. The idea exploded into public view in the 1990s with the
advent of direct-to-consumer advertising of prescription drugs, antidepressants
in particular. Harrington documents ad campaigns for Prozac and Zoloft that
assured wary customers the new medications were not simply treating patients’
symptoms by altering their consciousness, as recreational drugs might. Instead,
the medications were billed as repairing an underlying biological problem.
Better yet, a psychiatrist named Peter Kramer claimed that
Prozac would change your personality, even making you into someone else. It’s
clearly a sign of hybris and overreach.
So, Greenberg and Harrington blame the marketplace:
The
strategy worked brilliantly in the marketplace. But there was a catch.
“Ironically, just as the public was embracing the ‘serotonin imbalance’ theory
of depression,” Harrington writes, “researchers were forming a new consensus”
about the idea behind that theory: It was “deeply flawed and probably outright
wrong.” Stymied, drug companies have for now abandoned attempts to find new
treatments for mental illness, continuing to peddle the old ones with the same
claims. And the news has yet to reach, or at any rate affect, consumers. At
last count, more
than 12 percent of Americans ages 12 and older were taking antidepressants.
The chemical-imbalance theory, like the revamped DSM, may fail as science, but as rhetoric it has turned out to
be a wild success.
Again, this ignores the fact that many people find a benefit
in Prozac.
Nevertheless, the pretense involve in treating mental
illness as physical illness deserves to be exposed:
But by
virtue of its focus on our mental lives, and especially on our subjective
experience of the world and ourselves, psychiatry, far more directly than other
medical specialties, implicates our conception of who we are and how our lives
should be lived. It raises, in short, moral questions. If you convince people
that their moods are merely electrochemical noise, you are also telling them
what it means to be human, even if you only intend to ease their pain.
If such is the case, and I believe it is, psychiatry has
crossed another barrier. Its practitioners hold themselves up as authorities on
moral issues, on how to conduct one’s life. Surely, these issues matter. And
yet, there is nothing in medical training or in science itself that sets down
ethical rules. Science, David Hume famously wrote, is about "is." Ethics, he
continues, involves “should.” The two are constantly confused. We would do
better if we stopped looking to science for solutions to moral dilemmas.
Harrington is surely correct to suggest that psychiatry
should limit itself to brain diseases, which she calls severe mental illnesses.
And she wants psychiatry to open up dialogues with other fields, like social
sciences and humanities. If psychoses as brain diseases are most apt to receive
medical treatment, one has difficulty imagining why or how humanists could
contribute:
Harrington
ends her book with a plea that psychiatry become “more modest in focus” and
train its attention on the severe mental illnesses, such as schizophrenia, that
are currently treated largely in prisons and homeless shelters—an enterprise
that she thinks would require the field “to overcome its persistent reductionist
habits and commit to an ongoing dialogue with … the social sciences and even
the humanities.” This is a reasonable proposal, and it suggests avenues other
than medication, such as a renewed effort to create humane and effective
long-term asylum treatment. But no matter how evenhandedly she frames this
laudable proposal, an industry that has refused to reckon with the full
implications of its ambitions or the extent of its failures is unlikely to heed
it.
The most important problem with severe mental illness today
is getting treatment to the afflicted. As we have seen on many occasions, we as a society
have rejected the idea of committing such patients involuntarily to psychiatric
institutions. The fault does not lie with psychiatrists, but with bright-eyed
civil liberties attorneys who believe that people who refuse to accept that
they are ill should be allowed to run free in our society.
If it were up to
psychiatrists, many more schizophrenics would be hospitalized and would be in
position to be helped by modern medicine. In that case, the problem is the
civil liberties lobby and social scientists and humanists, people who have
never dealt with psychotics and who ascribe their condition to capitalist oppression.
4 comments:
The great Richard Mitchell said this many years ago about "educated" people:
"It is possible, of course, to keep educated people unfree in a state of civilization, but it’s much easier to keep ignorant people unfree in a state of civilization. And it is easiest of all if you can convince the ignorant that they are educated, for you can thus make them collaborators in your disposition of their liberty and property. That is the institutionally assigned task, for all that it may be invisible to those who perform it, of American public education. "
The exact same sentiment applies to the psycho community.
"Its practitioners hold themselves up as authorities on moral issues, on how to conduct one’s life. Surely, these issues matter. And yet, there is nothing in medical training or in science itself that sets down ethical rules. Science, David Hume famously wrote, is about "is." Ethics, he continues, involves “should.” The two are constantly confused. We would do better if we stopped looking to science for solutions to moral dilemmas."
Spot on. The fact team has appropriated the value team because the value team has quit the field entirely. But the distinction is not so clear cut as Weber would have it. The very best book I've ever read on this subject is by Leo Strauss, "Natural Right and History." Tough slog, but he gets right to the heart of the problem. Definitely worth the investment.
It's always "the marketplace" and "capitalist oppression" all the way down.
It's Pudding Time.
Post a Comment