Andrew Sullivan’s 1998 book on friendship, Love Undetectable, is somewhat dated,
but it is still worth mention and notice.
Maria Popova has recently done so on her Brain Pickings
blog, and, if her rendering is correct, Sullivan wrote an important book on a
topic that is often ignored.
Popova summarizes Sullivan:
He
argues that our world has failed to give friendship its due as “a critical
social institution, as an ennobling moral experience, as an immensely delicate
but essential interplay of the virtues required to sustain a fully realized human
being.”
Of course, friendship is the centerpiece of Aristotle’s
ethics. For the philosopher, friendship, as a voluntary social tie, requires good character. After all, the Greek word ethos
means character.
Aristotle’s book is a guide to building character. To get
along with other people, to develop and sustain a friendship you need to have
good character. It is far more important than emotional authenticity.
Sullivan summarizes Aristotle
well:
In Aristotle’s hermetically sane universe, the
instinct for human connection is so common and so self-evidently good that
there is little compunction to rule certain friendships out of the arc of human
friendliness. There is merely an attempt to understand and categorize each
instance of phila and to place each instance of the instinct in its natural and
ennobling place. Everything is true, Aristotle seems to say, so long as it is
never taken for anything more than it is. And so friendship belongs to the nod
of daily passengers on a commuter train, to the regular business client, and to
the ornery neighbor. It encompasses the social climber and the social
butterfly, the childhood crush and the lifelong soulmate. It comprises the
relationship between a boss and his employees, a husband and his wife, a
one-night stand and a longtime philanderer, a public official and his dubious
contributor.
Most importantly, Sullivan wants
to distinguish friendship from romantic love. He will eventually make the very
important point that our current cult to romantic love has militated against
friendships.
For the purposes of this blog,
what Sullivan calls a cult to romantic love bears the stamp of Freudian theory.
It also recalls Socrates’ remarks, channeling Diotima, in Plato's Symposium, to
the effect that Eros is not a god, but a daimon. Surely, it is not an
accident that the word is the forebear of our word, demon. Doesn't this tell
us that Eros is a demonic force?
Sullivan explains that friendship requires activity and that
it must be reciprocal:
Unlike a variety of other relationships,
friendship requires an acknowledgement by both parties that they are involved
or it fails to exist. One can admire someone who is completely unaware of our
admiration, and the integrity of that admiration is not lost; one may even
employ someone without knowing who it is specifically one employs; one may be
related to a great-aunt whom one has never met (and may fail ever to meet). And
one may, of course, fall in love with someone without the beloved being aware
of it or reciprocating the love at all. And in all these cases, the
relationships are still what they are, whatever the attitude of the other
person in them: they are relationships of admiration, business, family, or
love.
Moreover, you cannot force
someone to be your friend:
But friendship is different. Friendship uniquely
requires mutual self-knowledge and will. It takes two competent, willing people
to be friends. You cannot impose a friendship on someone, although you can
impose a crush, a lawsuit, or an obsession. If friendship is not reciprocated,
it simply ceases to exist or, rather, it never existed in the first place.
Friendship’s greatest enemy has
been the modern version of romantic love. Here Sullivan’s analysis is
brilliant:
The great modern enemy of friendship has turned
out to be love. By love, I don’t mean the principle of giving and mutual regard
that lies at the heart of friendship [but] love in the banal, ubiquitous,
compelling, and resilient modern meaning of love: the romantic love that
obliterates all other goods, the love to which every life must apparently lead,
the love that is consummated in sex and celebrated in every particle of our
popular culture, the love that is institutionalized in marriage and instilled
as a primary and ultimate good in every Western child. I mean eros, which is
more than sex but is bound up with sex. I mean the longing for union with
another being, the sense that such a union resolves the essential quandary of
human existence, the belief that only such a union can abate the loneliness
that seems to come with being human, and deter the march of time that threatens
to trivialize our very existence….
We live in a world, in fact, in which respect
and support for eros has acquired the hallmarks of a cult.
He continues:
Of course, the impossibility of love is partly
its attraction. It is an irrational act, a concession to the passions, a
willing renunciation of reason and moderation — and that’s why we believe in
it. It is also why, in part, the sober writers and thinkers of the ancient and
medieval worlds found it a self-evidently inferior, if bewitching, experience.
But their confidence in this regard was based not simply on a shrewd analysis
of love but on a deeper appreciation of friendship. Without the possibility of
friendship, after all, love might seem worth the price. If the promise of
union, of an abatement to loneliness, of finding a soulmate, was only available
through the vagaries of eros, then it might be worth all the heartbreak and
insanity for a glimpse, however brief, of what makes life worth living. But if
all these things were available in a human relationship that is not inherently
self-destructive, then why, after all, should one choose the riskier and weaker
option?
Where our therapy culture
suggests that when people are depressed they need to fall in love, Sullivan,
following Aristotle, suggests that it is far better to make a friend.
In his words:
And in almost every regard, friendship delivers
what love promises but fails to provide. The contrast between the two are, in
fact, many, and largely damning to love’s reputation. Where love is swift, for
example, friendship is slow. Love comes quickly, as the song has it, but
friendship ripens with time. If love is at its most perfect in its infancy,
friendship is most treasured as the years go by.
And also:
If love is sudden, friendship is steady. At the
moment of meeting a friend for the first time, we might be aware of an
immediate “click” or a sudden mutual interest. But we don’t “fall in
friendship.” And where love is often at its most intense in the period before
the lover is possessed, in the exquisite suspense of the chase, and the
stomach-fluttering nervousness of the capture, friendship can only really be
experienced when both friends are fully used to each other. For friendship is
based on knowledge, and love can be based on mere hope… You can love someone
more than you know him, and he can be perfectly loved without being perfectly
known. But the more you know a friend, the more a friend he is.
Romantic love is a passion. It
consumes those who get too close to it. It makes more and more imperious
demands, to the point where it appears to be insatiable:
Love affairs need immense energy, they demand a
total commitment and a capacity for pain. Friendship, in contrast, merely needs
tending. Although it is alive, a living, breathing thing, and can suffer from
neglect, friendship can be left for a while without terrible consequences.
Because it is built on the accumulation of past experiences, and not the fickle
and vulnerable promise of future ones, it has a sturdiness that love may often
lack, and an undemonstrative beauty that love would walk heedlessly past.
In a culture where passionate
intensity is the hallmark for authentic experience, friendship has unfortunately
been relegated to the shadows. All manner of relationships suffer for as much.
1 comment:
Much like marriage, a friendship takes two people working on it.
Post a Comment