Cue the “cleanliness is next to Godliness” music.
The researchers who were studying the impact of being
exposed to dirt, filth and insalubrious environments did not talk about
Godliness, but they did prove that feelings of disgust trigger bad behavior.
They also discovered that, when faced with something
disgusting, you can mitigate the negative ethical effects by conjuring an image
of Windex or Mr. Clean.
The press release from Rice University (via New York Magazine) summarizes the results:
While
feelings of disgust can increase behaviors like lying and cheating, cleanliness
can help people return to ethical behavior, according to a recent study by
marketing experts at Rice University, Pennsylvania State University and Arizona
State University. The study highlights the powerful impact emotions have on
individual decision-making.
“As an
emotion, disgust is designed as a protection,” said Vikas Mittal, the J. Hugh
Liedtke Professor of Marketing at Rice’s Jones Graduate School of Business.
“When people feel disgusted, they tend to remove themselves from a situation.
The instinct is to protect oneself. People become focused on ‘self’ and they’re
less likely to think about other people. Small cheating starts to occur: If I’m
disgusted and more focused on myself and I need to lie a little bit to gain a
small advantage, I’ll do that. That’s the underlying mechanism.”
In
turn, the researchers found that cleansing behaviors actually mitigate the
self-serving effects of disgust. “If you can create conditions where people’s
disgust is mitigated, you should not see this (unethical) effect,” Mittal said.
“One way to mitigate disgust is to make people think about something clean. If
you can make people think of cleaning products – for example, Kleenex or Windex
– the emotion of disgust is mitigated, so the likelihood of cheating also goes
away. People don’t know it, but these small emotions are constantly affecting
them.”
Disgust is adaptive. It tells people to withdraw in order to
protect themselves against a threat… presumably to their health. Disgust makes
people more selfish, but, under the circumstances selfishness is not a bad
thing.
Cleanliness, on the other hand, makes you want to interact
with other people, to seek out their company, to be considerate toward them.
Cleanliness tells you that it is safe to engage with other
people. Disgust tells you to disengage.
Of course, people who take care to be clean and who live in
a clean space are showing consideration already. Thus, when you engage with
them you are reciprocating.
Filthiness is not just an effort to distance yourself, but a
will, if need be, to act unethically. This suggests that when faced with
someone who has not washed for a month you are going to be less likely to act
ethically.
We also recognize that the principle can be misapplied. One
can certainly see groups of people as unclean when they are not. Such is the
nature of prejudice and bigotry.
One must add here that the role disgust plays in human
society has been questioned by, among others, philosopher Martha Nussbaum.
In an interview Nussbaum politicized the issue by dividing
emotions into those that serve a useful purpose and those that are used to
discriminate.
Among the first group are anger and fear:
Some
emotions are essential to law and to public principles of justice: anger at
wrongdoing, fear for our safety, compassion for the pain of others, all these
are good reasons to make laws that protect people in their rights. Of course
individual instances of anger, fear, and compassion may be misplaced, but in
the cases where they stand up to scrutiny, we should go ahead and make law in
response to those emotions. John Stuart Mill observed that in this way all of a
society's ideas about law and justice might be seen as built on anger and fear.
When it comes to disgust, Nussbaum sees things differently:
Disgust,
I argue (drawing on recent psychological research), is different. Its cognitive
content involves a shrinking from contamination that is associated with a human
desire to be non-animal. That desire, of course, is irrational in the sense
that we know we will never succeed in fulfilling it; it is also irrational in
another and even more pernicious sense. As psychological research shows, people
tend to project disgust properties onto groups of people in their own society,
who come to figure as surrogates for people's anxieties about their own
animality. By branding members of these groups as disgusting, foul, smelly,
slimy, the dominant group is able to distance itself even further from its own
animality. Such irrational projections have been involved in antisemitism
through the ages, and in misogyny in more or less every society. They are also
involved in more localized forms of discrimination, such as the traditional Hindu
caste hierarchy, or American discrimination against homosexuals.
Unlike
anger, disgust does not provide the disgusted person with a set of reasons that
can be used for the purposes of public argument and public persuasion. If my
child has been murdered and I am angry at that, I can persuade you that you
should share those reasons; if you do, you will come to share my outrage. But
if someone happens to feel that gay men are disgusting, that person cannot
offer any reasoning that will persuade someone to share that emotion; there is
nothing that would make the dialogue a real piece of persuasion.
She does recognize the possibility that disgust might be
adaptive but dismissing it because it has often been misapplied:
I
believe disgust had an evolutionary function, by giving emphasis and force to
the sense of danger. Even if disgust doesn't perfectly track danger, it is
close enough as a heuristic, when we have no time to perform the needed
inquiry, or are unable to perform it. Even today, when we have many ways of
finding out about danger, the sense of disgust is a useful heuristic. If the
milk smells disgusting, it's a pretty good rule not to drink it. We can't all
the time be testing our environment for bacteria, so staying away from what
disgusts is good practice. But I think this shows nothing about the utility of
the projective form of disgust, in which we deem certain groups of people
disgusting and assimilate them to feces, corpses, and disgusting animals. That may
be a ubiquitous human activity, but ubiquity doesn't prove value, especially
not ethical and political value. The ubiquity of the male domination of women
doesn't show that this domination is ethically or politically good.
But, if you believe, as Nussbaum seems to, that men have
always oppressed women, how does her theory explain why men are attracted to
women, when they seek them out and do not, in most cases shun them or run away
from them.
And yet, all sex acts are not created equal. All do not bear
the same risk to one’s health. Some people find promiscuous sexual
activity disgusting, but doesn’t that reflect the fact that greater
promiscuity entails a greater health risk?
Nussbaum seems to believe in the family of humanity, but
most human beings divide people into friends, foes and strangers.
There is nothing irrational about seeking out people who
resemble us more closely or with whom we have more in common.
Surely, this ability to draw distinctions can be abused or
misapplied, but the same is true of any moral principle.
Ultimately, Nussbaum does not like disgust because she links
it to shame, which punishes people by ostracizing them.
She explains:
Disgust,
by contrast, expresses a wish to separate oneself from a source of pollution;
its social reflex is to run away. When I am disgusted by certain American
politicians, I fantasize moving away to Finland—a country in which I have
worked a little, and which I see as a pure blue and green place of unpolluted
lakes, peaceful forests, and pristine social-democratic values. And I don't
know it enough to know its faults. To fantasize about moving to Finland is not
a constructive response to present American problems.
And yet, there are times when you ought to run away. You
might not have the resources to clean the Augean stables. You might do well to avoid people whose
hygiene is seriously deficient.
If you eliminate shame, as Nussbaum wants to do, you are
left with guilt as the only acceptable social sanction. Is it really better to
criminalize all of the behaviors you reject?
Is it really such a bad thing to encourage people—through extra-legal
means—to practice good decorum, propriety and integrity? And if you discover
that certain people are morally deficient, isn’t it a good idea to break off
contacts with them?
After all, you are known by the company you keep.
5 comments:
Shame has won the day at least for plantary scientist Matt Taylor who thoughtlessly wore a naughty shirt while being interviewed on TV, and after being called out by feminists, apologized with tearful remorse, whether or not to their satisfaction.
http://pjmedia.com/eddriscoll/2014/11/14/the-wrong-stuff-2/
If this is how shame is supposed to work, it succeeded perfectly, and now an otherwise oblivious scientist will think a bit harder what he wears when he might be on TV.
But really, it more seems to be about guilt than shame. A person who feels guilt can quickly and easily apologize, but a person who feels shame, who knows his sexist feelings are wrong, and disgusting, well, that makes apologizing harder.
And that's part of the problem. If the goal is to convince Matt Taylor he was negligent in his shirt choice that day, then the femininsts can forgive him. But if the goal is to get him to admit it is wrong to objectivize women then any apology short of saying "I'll never wear such a shirt again" is not good enough.
So I'd guess the feminists need to keep the pressure up, and not forgive him, because those tears were not sincere, because he didn't admit he'll never ever do it again.
Assuming that “fear for our safety” is “essential to law and to public principles of justice”, doesn’t it follow that the statement, “We have nothing to fear but fear itself”, is monumentally foolish?
I’ve always thought that it was; at least now I have philosopher Martha Nussbaum to back me up.
He should have said, "A woman with a gun is empowered. I support that. Are you against empowerment?"
I have to admit I think some of this is an example of how feminism is killing itself.
5 reasons why:
http://legalinsurrection.com/2014/11/5-reasons-feminists-cant-complain-about-comet-scientists-shirt/
Walking around dressed as lady parts pale to the man's shirt. Damn this stuff is funny. Come back and bother me when your hypocrisy isn't so glaring.
Then please explain:
1. Why people stop to stare at a gruesome car accident?
2. Why do/did people widely attend public hangings?
3. Why do people say things like: Eww! this is disgusting - here you try it!
Generally - disgust and dirt and terrible behavior is attractive, not repulsive. Florence Nightingale effect. Rubbernecking... Or women who "fall in love" with serial killer or rapist men...
Come on! Fight or flight. Curiosity. The need for thrill or escape. This drives large numbers of humans -- including women - to choose and stay with 'bad' partners...
So... what do women what? The same things men what... enough excitement to make it interesting. For some women that's sex once a week -- for others that a motorcycle ride with a serial killer.
Post a Comment